Saturday 25 May 2013

Should Britain Retain its Nuclear Deterrent?


The bullet points below summarise what I take to be the main lines of the arguments for and against Britain renewing its nuclear deterrent capability.  A decision on this is due to be taken by the Government in 2016.  The timetable is necessary because some of the equipment used by the current deterrence system - the submarines - is due to be retired during the 2020s.  The issue is thus likely to feature prominently at the likley General Election in May 2015, especially as there are genuine differences between the three main parties on the issue.  As of the time of writing in 2013, the Conservatives are the most pro-nuclear party and the Liberal Democrats the most anti, with Labour somewhere in the middle.

Arguments Against (Principled):
  • Disarmament by Britain may encourage others to follow suit.
  • Cost: spending on nuclear weapons is a disgrace when so many go hungry.
  • Use of nuclear weapons is against international law.
  • Use of nuclear weapons is necessarily immoral.
Arguments Against (Pragmatic):
  • Some other countries seem to get by just fine without it.
  • The nuclear deterrent is a case of generals fighting the last war. 
  • Cost: Britain can no longer afford it.
Arguments For Renewal:
  • It buys us a seat at the top table.
  • The program keeps a significant number of people in work.
  • The threat from North Korea, Iran, and other rogue states.
  • Nuclear deterrence makes conventional wars less likely.
  • Climate change implies an uncertain future for the world.
I will deal with the arguments against renewal first, starting with the ones I have dubbed "principled" - by which I mean that these arguments, if sound, would have force not only in Britain today, but in any country at any time.  Those I have labelled "pragmatic", by contrast, depend for their force on the particular circumstances of early 21st century Britain.  I will then examine the arguments for renewal, before summarizing and offering a conclusion.

Section 1: Arguments Against (Principled)

1.1: Disarmament as a way of encouraging others to follow suit

I think that the weakest of the arguments against nuclear disarmament is that it might be expected to promote general disarmament.  The basic problem with this argument is that it greatly overrates Britain's influence in the world.  I find it highly implausible that British disarmament would bear significantly on the decisions of other nuclear powers, such as China, India, Pakistan, Russia and Israel, each of which will have become nuclear states for reasons that seem utterly compelling to them, and would be baffled at the suggestion that they should disarm just because Britain has.  To the extent that other nuclear powers took note of British disarmament at all, they would probably interpret it as a sign of weakness.

Furthermore, there are already countries that have given up nuclear power status, having formerly possessed weapons (notably South Africa), but this does not seem to have inclined other nuclear states in general to give up in imitation.  (In South Africa's case the major reason for giving up its weapons program was to help bring about an end to the country's international isolation - a factor that does not apply to most other nuclear states, including Britain).


1.2: Spending on nuclear weapons is a disgrace when so many go hungry

I think that this attempt to link the issues of nuclear deterrence and famine relief fails, for the following reason: the first duty of any government is to protect the safety of its citizens.  This means that helping people out in other parts of the world, however desperate their plight, must have a lower priority than self-protection.  Of course, if nuclear deterrence turns out not to be necessary for our self-protection, then the money spent it should indeed be spent on something else - quite possibly on aid to the hungry.  But to establish that this is the case we would need an independent argument to demonstrate that nuclear deterrence is unnecessary for self-defence, and that argument alone would settle the issue concerning the renewal of the nuclear deterrent, with no need to refer to the desirability of alternative spending priorities.

In actual fact, we are not so short of money that we are forced to choose between maintaining our defences and meeting our obligations to the world's poor.  We rank reasonably well in the OECDs league table of international aid donors - 9th out of 23 in the rankings according the the percentage of GDP spent on overseas aid in 2009 (and the 8 countries that ranked higher than Britain were all smaller countries, each having at most a quarter of Britain's population).  Of course, someone may take the view that the OECDs performance on aid is not good enough and that we therefore ought to donate much more.  But if we are to do this we must identify some other item of expenditure that we can do without, and I can see no particular reason why the nuclear deterrent should automatically be chosen for this role, as opposed to, say, some part of the 95% of the national defence budget that is spent on non-nuclear defence.  And with any of the defence budget, if it is not necessary for our defence, then it should be scrapped regardless of whatever else the money will be spent on, and if it is necessary for our defence, then it should not be scrapped, again regardless of whatever else the money could be spent on.

In practice, the point of linking the arms industry and global poverty in this way is to appeal to the emotions, rather than to make a strictly rational argument.  We should, however, prefer rational argument to emotional pleas in a case like this one where the issues are complex, and the consequences of a poor decision could be far-reaching.

1.3: The use of nuclear weapons is against international law

The legal arguments surrounding this seem to be fairly involved (see this Wikipedia article for a more detailed discussion).  In one sense the use of nuclear weapons is illegal, as it almost inevitably involves civilian casualties on a huge scale, and hence fails to distinguish between combatants and non-combatants, as customary international law requires.  On the other hand, there seems to be some doubt about whether it would be illegal to use nuclear weapons in "extreme circumstance[s] of self defence" (ibid.), and also about whether the illegality of using the weapons also translates into its being illegal just to possess them if they remain unused.  However, rather than get stuck into these debates (which probably requires legal training), I want to instead explore a quite different possibility - namely, that there are some circumstances is which it would be prudential, and perhaps even morally right, to set international law aside.  

Laws play a role in complex systems of social organisation (civilisations) that preserve peace and order and thus enable the individuals who participate in them to enjoy satisfactory lives.  People who live in organised societies learn to regard obedience to the law as both prudent and morally praiseworthy, as they must for society to remain organised.  However, whilst the normalisation of these learned associations is a necessary condition for the preservation of civilisation, it is probably not a sufficient condition.  For instance, natural disaster, economic collapse or defeat in war could all bring about the collapse of social organisation and a descent into lawlessness.  Should such a collapse happen, then most of the people who live through it will retain the learned associations that automatically prompt them to obey the law, even though law and order has broken down.  But, should they continue to act on the prompts as they would have done before the collapse?  Would it, for instance, be prudent (or even moral) to refuse to take food from shops without paying, even if civilisation had irretrievably broken down and there was no means of paying?  I think the most sensible judgement would be that at least some of the laws which previously governed the exchange of goods had become inoperative and so should be disregarded.

International law plays the same role in the "international community" as domestic laws play within individual countries - that is, it defines and reinforces an ideal of civilized behaviour which, as long as it remains generally accepted, should preserve a relatively peaceful state of affairs in that community.  However, the international community is much more volatile than the domestic societies of all but the most unstable individual countries.  I conjecture that this is because the norms that underpin social organisation evolved first amongst small groups, and refinements of those norms that underpin larger social units only began to evolve as transport and communications technology improved and commerce spread.  A truly global community has only begun to emerge in the last five centuries or so, and is thus still relatively immature.  This immaturity makes it prone to occasional lapses back into the chaotic Hobbesian "state of nature", as happened between 1914 and (roughly) 1953, when an international order that had been relatively settled for most of the nineteenth century suddenly collapsed into a series of world wars, violent revolutions, totalitarian dictatorships, civil wars, genocides and other mass killings of civilians (including the only ever uses so far of nuclear weapons).  The international order has again remained relatively settled since 1953 (the end of the Korean War, since when the acknowledged Great Powers have never been directly at war with each other), and this long period of relative calm has encouraged the development of a substantial body of international law, and the establishment of international courts to interpret it.

It is right that we should abide by international law for as long as the current international order remains relatively settled - and this means that any actual use of nuclear weapons is clearly off-limits.  But does this also mean that we should not possess them either, on the grounds that there is no point in buying a weapon that you are definitely not going to use under any circumstances?  Not necessarily, because there is no guarantee that the international order will remain stable - indeed, another reversion to chaos could quite conceivably be triggered by the fallout from climate change some time in the 21st century.  If that were to happen, then laws drawn up in more peaceful times would cease to be reliable guides to morality and prudence, so that it might be right to set them aside in some circumstances.  Judging by the Wikipedia debate referenced at the start of this section, some legal judgements already incorporate caveats that allow for this setting-aside in case of extreme national emergency; but as this appears to be a point of controversy amongst legal experts I have chosen to make a political case for, in effect, treating the law as if it does contain those caveats.  If it did not contain them, then the law would have failed to recognise the nature of the political realities that bought it into being - that the law is an artifact of peace; and that, although the law helps to preserve peace, it is not so much use in bringing peace about in the first place.

The major upshot of all this is that we can purchase and own nuclear weapons with no intention of using them save in a dire emergency comparable with the World Wars of the early 20th century - and we can do this consistently with international law, unless the law is interpreted in a way that makes it an ass, in which case we are justified in ignoring it.  A secondary upshot is that it is better that the law should allow appropriate leeway to deal with such emergencies, as this will increase the chances of building a continuous legal tradition robust enough to survive periods of chaos in international relations.

1.4: Use of nuclear weapons is necessarily immoral

OK, so lets imagine that we do enter another Hobbesian "state of nature" in international affairs sometime in the fairly near future.  Could it ever be moral (as opposed to prudential) to use nuclear weapons in such a situation?  Considering the last chaotic period, 1914-53, may provide some clues (incidentally, I think there have been other chaotic periods, at least in European history: 1618-48 and 1789-1815 for example; but 1914-53 looks to be the only world-wide example).

First question: considering the global power struggle that took place in the early 20th-century as a whole, is it possible to say that any party to it was more moral than any other party?  It is plain that the key players (Britain, Germany, France, the USA, Russia, China and Japan) would have stopped at almost nothing to secure victory over their rivals.  As an example, Winston Churchill, who led Britain from 1940-45, was a staunch lifelong anti-Communist - but when it became necessary for Britain to ally with Soviet Russia he did so without any hesitation, famously commenting that, had Germany invaded Hell, he would "at least make a favourable reference to the Devil in the House of Commons."  Innumerable other examples could be deployed to make the same point - that once national survival became the over-riding priority, every other consideration went out of the window.  Since all of the powers would have slaughtered innocents in order to win (and most of them did), how can we regard any of them as "moral"?  

Of course, it was to be expected that once one power (or a combination of them) had prevailed over the others, then some semblance of international order would be restored, and all countries could resume (relatively) civilised behaviour.  But as this could be expected to happen whoever won, it is not enough to confer superior morality on any party to the conflict to observe that that party is fighting to restore order - they were all fighting to restore order, i.e. their own.

I suggest that the only way we can make a moral distinction between the warring powers is to ask what kind of world order they were each seeking to establish, and which among them would best promote human flourishing in the long run.  This is ultimately a political judgement, but that doesn't mean we should be shy of making it.  After Britain and France had thrown in their lot with the USA the three of them stood for what we now call "liberal democracy"; Russia and (from 1949) China stood for what might loosely be termed communism; Germany and Japan (from the 1930s until their respective defeats in 1945) stood for what be loosely termed fascism.  I think that liberal democracy is by a long distance the least bad of these three alternatives, and on that basis I argue that the Western Allies had right on their side in during this period of conflict.

So, does this make the USA's use of nuclear weapons in 1945 morally right (or, for that matter, Britain's use, in 1942-45, of aerial bombing tactics designed to cause mass slaughter on a scale comparable with that caused by the later nuclear strikes)?  Or, to resort to cliche, does the end justify the means?  Well, actually, I am not saying the ends justify the means, but something a little more complicated: the means being used by all sides were such as to turn the struggle into a free-for-all; and, given that this was so and that the Allies couldn't do anything to change it, the extreme undesirability of a victory for the totalitarian states imposed on them a duty to pursue victory by whatever means were necessary. 

Given this intellectual framework, the 1945 nuclear attack on Japan can be justified.  Clearly, if by some (extraordinarily improbable) sequence of events, Japan were to acquire a Fascist-inclined government in a 2013-world otherwise unchanged from our own, we would not deal with that situation by attacking Japan with nuclear bombs - and nor would we be justified in doing so.  Most likely, we would deal with Japan in much the same way that we generally deal with "rogue states" - a mixture mainly of economic sanctions, diplomatic cold-shouldering and defensive military alliances with neighbouring states.  But, whilst the real-life Japan of 1945 had already been divested of most of the overseas conquests it had been making since 1931, and probably lacked the capacity to launch new wars of aggression, the real issue was the need to restore international stability and order in the name of liberal democracy - something which, because of the particular way the struggle had evolved, required the unconditional surrenders of both Germany and Japan.  In Japan's case, it was judged necessary to demonstrate a willingness to use the "most cruel" new weapon in order to bring this about quickly.

I realise that all this pragmatism sounds rather brutal; but I think it is important to recognise that: (i) liberal democracy's emphatic defeat of its enemies in WW2 has been essential to the spread of the democratic way of life after 1950 to not just Europe and North America, but much of Asia, Latin America and (more recently) even Africa and the Middle East;  (ii) this spread has already improved the lives of hundreds of millions of people, and has the potential to continue; (iii) that this good outweighs the harm done to the smaller numbers of innocent victims of Allied nuclear (and conventional) bombing; and that (iv) the Allied leaders were fully aware at the time of the bombings that something like (i), (ii) and (iii) were likely to transpire - witness Churchill's 1940 prophecy that should the Allies win "all Europe may be freed and the life of the world may move forward into broad, sunlit uplands".

The actual use (as opposed to mere possession) of the nuclear bomb would, I concede, require something analogous to these extraordinary circumstances in order to be morally justified.  An opponent of nuclear weapons might then argue that such circumstances are so unlikely to occur again that the possibility should be discounted.  However, any such argument must be premised on the stability of the current liberal democratic international order - and, as many critics of nuclear weapons are also unimpressed with liberal democracy, this line of argument may not appeal to many of them.  In any case, the significant possibility of catastrophic climate change undercuts the premise.  I therefore conclude that the future occurrence of circumstances that would make the use of nuclear weapons morally justified cannot be ruled out.



This concludes my treatment of what I have dubbed the "principled" arguments against nuclear weapons.  As the first two of those arguments (for British disarmament as a way to promote general disarmament; and for using the money spent on nuclear weapons to alleviate world poverty) are, in my opinion, relatively weak, I have dealt with them quite briefly.  The other two arguments against  nuclear weapons (on the grounds of the illegality of actually using them; and, finally, of the immorality of so doing) I have treated at greater length, because I think that some interesting philosophical territory needs to be traversed in the search for acceptable replies to them.  However, I think such replies, along the lines I have sketched out, are available, and, given the more thorough treatment that I haven't the space for here, would be enough to do the job of answering all of the "principled" objections to nuclear arms.

Section 2: Arguments Against (Pragmatic)

Now, it is time to turn to what I have called the "pragmatic" arguments for Britain abandoning its deterrent in the review scheduled for 2016.

2.1: Some other countries seem to get by just fine without it

A pretty diverse collection of countries do seem to get by just fine without any nuclear deterrent capability, in the sense that their populations do not show obvious signs of living in fear of nuclear attack - for instance: Spain, Belgium, Poland, Sweden, Australia, Singapore, Thailand, Japan, Mexico, and the entire continents of South America and Africa - that is to say, countries that are not at all similar in their general political orientation, and many of which are far from having any discernable history of pacifism.  Indeed, only 9 jurisdictions out of a total of 206 currently possess nuclear weapons.  So, why don't we just join the non-nuclear club, and save ourselves a whole load of money and hassle?

The thought is reinforced by a quick look at the nine nuclear states.  Five of them rank in the top ten of the world's most populous countries, and so might be expected to be prepared to shoulder the costs that come with playing a leading role in world affairs.  Of the others, Israel counts as a special case owing to its unique security situation; and it doesn't seem like a recommendation for any club that the North Korean dictatorship can be numbered among its members.  The numbers are made up by Britain and France, both of whom became permanent members of the UN Security Council after WW2, largely on account of the influence they used to have in the world before that conflagaration, rather than the influence they still have.  Arguably, it is their attachment to their status as permanent members of the Security Council which explains their enthusiasm for nuclear deterrence, rather than any real security needs (the five permanent members are the same five countries to be the only ones recognised as "legitimate" nuclear powers under the Nuclear Non-Proliferation Treaty - a congruence that seems to imply that giving up nuclear weapons might lead to a downgrade of status in the Security Council - I will say more about this in section 3.1).

So is it about time we hung up our warheads, pinned up a "Dun-Nuking" sign over the white cliffs of Dover and retired peacefully from the world stage?  I think there are two points that tell against: firstly, there is a moral consideration resulting from our former possession of a large colonial empire; and, secondly, there is the fact that we have a tradition of involvement in world affairs that once gone would be hard to re-build.  (Because this is the "pragmatic" section of the essay I think it is appropriate that my treatment of this question helps itself to the implicit assumptions that being prominent in world affairs is virtuous, and that maintaining a nuclear deterrent is an effective way to achieve such prominence.  I am taking the pragmatic aspect of the debate to centre around the question of how virtuous Britain should seek to be in its current circumstances).

The first point is simply that, owing to the history of the past 500 years, it would be a very different matter for Britain to opt out of international affairs than it would for Sweden, Poland, et al.  A significant part (how much is anyone's guess) of the UK's wealth exists because of its dominance of the world in the 18th and 19th centuries - a fact which does not apply to most other countries. Whether or not our gains were well-gotten is only marginally relevant to this point, which is that we gained handsomely from an international system of free trade and colonial governance that we put and place and laregely ran for a couple of centuries or so.  In doing this we shaped the histories of many countries for both good and ill.  To the extent that has been to the good it is only natural and right that we should want to defend our legacy; and to the extent that it has been to the bad it is equally natural and right that we should want to atone for the resulting damage.  Both impulses tend towards the UK's playing a larger role in international affairs than countries which have a smaller share of responsibility for the world's being the way it is today.

The second point concerns tradition; that is, established custom and practice.  Britain is simply used to playing a large role in international politics.  This is a matter of its voters, politicians, soldiers, diplomats, journalists, etc., etc. having certain kinds of expectations about what goes on.  But it is also a matter of the expectations of different groups being interconnected in a fairly complex way: for instance, we have a tradition (unlike Sweden) of producing young people who actually want to fight in wars; and journalists and other opinion-formers who will judge a government (in part) by its ability to maintain Britain's traditional "punching above our weight" stance.  My (admittedly speculative) proposal here is that these two apparently disparate traits (as well as others) have co-evolved in a way that makes us specially equipped to play a prominent role on the world stage; and so if we were to precipitately abandon this role then several aspects of the national psyche would be thrown out of kilter, resulting in a collective feeling of disorientation.

Of course, the argument of the previous paragraph should not be used to try to prove too much: that our current role in the world should be perpetually preserved.  If it is allowed to stand it shows only that changes in our role should be gradual, in order to allow our national character time to adapt (this actually fits well with my overall conclusion, which I will start developing in the next sub-section).  It also suggests a converse point which reinforces the conclusion: that some of the countries which will eventually need to play a much larger international role (e.g. Brazil, Germany, Nigeria, India) may also need time to adapt to their new roles, for similar reasons.  And also another point: that countries that have been pacific for a long time (e.g. Sweden) are to some extent locked in to staying that way - and this undermines any attempt to take those countries as role models for Britain, which is not similarly locked in.  Given the undesirability of all advanced countries becoming pacific at the same time, it is best to tolerate the fact that accidents of history have made some pacific and others warlike.  As one of the (relatively) warlike countries, we shouldn't be jealous of the pacific countries, as what their status gains them in money and comfort, it also costs them in prestige and influence; instead, we should aim to play our allotted role with good grace for as long as it lasts (which won't be forever).

2.2: The nuclear deterrent is a case of generals fighting the last war

The objection here is that Britain's continuous at-sea nuclear deterrence system was designed for the Cold War, which finished in 1991.  The threats we face today - small groups of terrorists that can flit from one place to the next - couldn't be more different than that posed by the Soviet Union - a huge, monolithic empire sustained by conventional and nuclear armed force.  If our conventional and nuclear forces (roughly) matched that of the Soviets, then we could contain them within fairly settled border long enough for the limitations of their economic system to become a crippling disadvantage to them.  Meanwhile, mutual deterrence ensured that a pre-emptive nuclear strike by either side was too risky to be worth seriously contemplating (although apparently Mao Tse-Tung would have been up for it if the Soviets had been).

Today, there is nothing like that nuclear stand-off between two global systems of thought, although there are more limited actual and potential nuclear stand-offs, e.g. India/Pakistan, North Korea/USA, Israel/Iran.  Given that Britain is remote from those more limited stand-offs, and likely to remain so, does not the (apparently irrevocable) end of the global stand-off render our deterrent redundant?  What is needed now is not a bomb that can flatten whole cities, but  precision instruments that can target individual al-Qaeda safe houses or training camps.  The argument suggests the conclusion that, given the nature of our most likely future enemies, nuclear weapons are simply a waste of money.
Of course, the terrorists might in theory acquire nuclear bombs, either from a rogue state or from criminal elements (although this seems to be unlikely just at the moment).  But if they did, would our bombs be as effective a deterrent to the enemy as was the case in the Cold War?  Well, you clearly can't flatten a whole city of innocents just to wipe out a few terrorist cells - and in any case many of them have little to lose, having already embraced martyrdom; so maybe our deterrent would become ineffective against a terrorist group that acquired nuclear bombs but still retained full independence of action.  But in the event that they acquired bombs with the help of rogue states, then those states would want some influence over their use; and deterrence should still work against rogue states, whose leaders have plenty to lose.  In practice, this probably serves as more of a deterrent against rogue states sharing any of their nuclear capability with terrorists in the first place, as any nuclear strike by terrorists would probably bring down fierce (possibly nuclear) retribution on rogue states, who would likely be blamed for the attacks even if culpability could not be proven.  Indeed, the 2003 invasion of Iraq following the mass murder in New York in 2001 could be read as a sign of just how the world would react to such an attack.

The argument of the preceding paragraph suggests that our possession of a deterrent does in fact restrain terrorist behaviour, albeit indirectly.  I also think that another strong argument against the obsolescence of nuclear weapons is available, in the form of climate change.  The fallout from climate change is likely to be quite dramatic, but no-one knows exactly what it will be, or how suddenly it could strike.  Conceivably, it could set the Great Powers of the world against each other in a way that hasn't been seen since the first half of the 20th century, in which case we would want to be well armed.  As I will elaborate this point further later on I won't labour it here.  Instead, I'll conclude by conceding that the argument against renewal from obsolescence does have some force; at least to the extent that we no longer need an arsenal of weapons capable of matching the Soviet Union's arsenal.  Continuous at-sea deterrence doesn't seem relevant to dealing with terrorists or rogue states, who would most likely be able to deliver just one strike, rather than the kind of strategic attack on our communications and defence network designed to destroy our ability to respond.  So, although the end of the Cold War might not have made nuclear weapons obsolete per se, I think it does give Britain good grounds for seeking out cheaper options than the current system, which uses four submarines on the basis that one is normally holed up in maintenance, and two more are quite likely to be in port or in use on training exercises.  If deterrence (against terrorists and rogue states) doesn't need to be absolutely continuous then perhaps we could go down to three, or even just two submarines.


2.3: Cost: Britain can no longer afford it

Which brings us neatly (I hope) onto the subject of cost.  I have found it a little tricky to find out how much the costs actually are, as the Trident system is quite complex.  As well as the four Vanguard-class submarines, there are the actual missiles from which the whole system gets its name; and then the warheads; then the bases at Faslane and Coulport; then the infrastructure tied up the command & control systems; then the running costs.  The most expensive elements in the system are hardware items, for which the cost is most properly represented as an annual depreciation charge (rather than the one-off outlay that shows up if you focus on cash-flow) - but what that charge should be depends on how long the hardware is expected to remain in use; and there is considerable controversy about this point.  The 2006 white paper that proposed a full-blooded replacement for Trident that would retain fully continuous at-sea deterrence, put the costs at £20bn capital outlay, and £1.5bn running costs (2006 prices).  Given a lifetime for the replacement of 20 years that makes the annual cost £2.5bn per year, which is just over 5% of the defence budget, which in turn takes just under 3% of Britain's GDP (it is worth noting that critics of the program dispute these figures).

As I don't want to get bogged down in budgetary detail, I am going to offer some fairly impressionistic observations:
  • Firstly, the cost of replacing Trident clearly isn't going to bring us to our knees as a nation.
  • Also clearly, we shouldn't expect other areas of life to be transformed on the back of diverting funds away from nuclear weapons, given the relatively modest size of our overall budget they currently take.
  • Even more clearly, the sums involved are very substantial (the expense is in the same ball-park as "HS2" - the extension of high-speed rail to the North of England - to which cost has been a prominent objection).
  • And, the spending is optional, in the sense that we don't absolutely have to do it.  This is in contrast to many areas of spending (health, education, pensions and so on) in which the effects of a simple cessation of spending would be immediately catastrophic.
  • As of the time of writing (2013) Britain is running a large public budget deficit, equivalent to 7.4% of GDP.
  • Therefore, the Trident renewal decision should be very carefully scrutinized with a view to making savings.
The arguments put forward in sections 1.1 - 1.4 and section 2.1 tend to suggest that Britain should keep some form of nuclear deterrent, whereas section 2.2 suggests that the Trident system gives us more deterrence than we really need going forwards.  Combining the strong pressure to look for savings discussed in this section with the opportunity to find them offered by 2.2 suggests that we should look to retain some kind of deterrent, but at lower cost than in the past. 

It now just remains to run through various arguments sometimes made for nuclear deterrence, to see if any of them will force a change to this putative conclusion.

Section 3: Arguments For Renewal

3.1: It buys us a seat at the top table

This point seems to crop up quite often in political discourse on the subject.  The thought is that, were we to give up the independent deterrent, we could expect to lose our traditional status as one of the more prominent countries in world affairs.  As a particular symbol of this more general loss, we might be expected to have to give up our permanent seat on the UN Security Council (one of the five seats, out of the total fifteen, that carries the right to veto any resolution).

I think that, as argument in favour of deterrent-renewal, this point has a fatal weakness that is not normally recognised.  To get straight to this weakness, I will grant the implicit assumptions that (i) a high place in the world is a good thing; and, (ii), that abandoning or downgrading our deterrent might compromise this place.  My point is that places on the UN Security Council (and other bodies) are not actually for sale - so no-one can "buy" them.  Therefore, if we spend £25bn on weapons because we take ourselves to be buying such a thing, we are highly likely to be disappointed with the results.  

This is because much of the institutional framework within which world politics is conducted is simply out-of-date.  The UN, for instance, dates back to the immediate aftermath of World War II - a moment in history when the British Empire still (notionally) ruled a quarter of the globe, the USA and Russia were the only truly global powers, and Europe was divided, occupied and in ruins.  The pressures mounting for reform of that institutional structure arise from the dramatic changes in the world balance of power since 1945 - namely: the emergence of a united and independent Europe; the rise of regional superpowers such as India and China, Brazil; and rapid economic growth and industrialisation that makes a nonsense of the old idea of a "third world".  These pressures have already resulted in the effective replacement of the G8 by the G20 as the world's leading economic forum (diluting Britain's share of that table from 12.5% to 5%), and are certain to lead to reform of the UN at some stage.  It is surely incredible to think that Britain could hold up this reform by pointing to its continued possession of nuclear weapons. 

I therefore conclude that this argument for the renewal of the deterrent, although popular, actually has no force at all.

3.2: The program keeps a significant number of people in work

Estimates of the number of jobs that depend on the Trident program vary.  In this linked press article (Herald Scotland Press Article) different parties claim that the number could be as low as 520 (if only direct employment is counted), or as high as 11,000 (if estimates of indirect employment effects are allowed).  As it would take a lot of digging around into the facts to establish which of these figures should be believed, and I have not really got the inclination or time to do this, I prefer to make two points that are not so dependent on these disputed facts. 

Firstly, if no-one ever got made redundant from any job, our economy could never evolve.  If the argument for renewal on employment grounds is framed as an argument against any changes whatsoever that will have employment effects then this would be an absurd consequence for that argument.  Therefore, the argument is only good (if it is good at all) for resisting over-rapid change in employment patterns.  Which in turn leads to my second point: that even 11,000 job losses spaced over 20 years (the approximate time-scale of the renewal project) still works out at only 550 losses per year, which is fairly small in terms of the Scottish economy's ability to absorb them and retrain the workers for other jobs.  Abandoning Trident will therefore not create a situation similar to that in 1980s Britain when whole regions of the country rapidly deindustrialised leaving workers with little hope of re-training and finding other jobs.  For the individual workers involved, any job losses may be a severe setback; but as a society, we generally accept that the aggregate balance of advantage must prevail over individual interests in collective decision-making.

My conclusion is that our second (politically popular) argument for renewal is in fact just as duff as the first.

3.3: The threat from North Korea, Iran, and other rogue states

This, I think, is a more promising argument.  On the face of it, if rogue states have (or may soon acquire) nuclear weapons, then surely we need the ultimate insurance policy against becoming a target ourselves?  When I touched on this point briefly, in section 2.2, I suggested a counter-argument, that the rogue states are geographically distant from Britain, and that we were not their principle adversaries.  However, this counter-argument leaves several hostages to fortune - that the geopolitical situation won't change; that existing rogue states won't develop long-range missile technology; and that people who generally detest our way of life won't take nuclear disarmament to be a sign of weakness.  As any of these situations could change quite quickly, and it takes a very long time to commission submarines and missile systems, we need to consider threats that might possibly emerge during the lifetime of the system rather than just the threats that are immediately apparent now.

The answer to these points developed in section 2.2 conceded that, although the ultimate insurance policy was still worth having to deal with these possible future threats, it no longer needed to be an insurance policy against a co-ordinated pre-emptive nuclear strike such as was envisioned at the height of the Cold War, as no rogue state is close to being able to launch such an attack - and, plausibly, none could ever get to this stage because the existing Great Powers would combine to prevent this.  This line of argument tends to suggest that Britain should continue to have a deterrent, but a cheaper one than the one it has at the moment.

3.4: Nuclear deterrence makes conventional wars less likely

The claim that nuclear weapons make conventional war less likely is hard to evaluate, because the development and proliferation of nuclear weapons in the era 1945-present has coincided with other trends that might also be expected to make conventional wars less likely (at least among leading states).  One such trend is the increasing interdependence of the leading economies; another is the spread of democracy (democracies are less likely to go to war with each other); another is that better education and greater prosperity make people less susceptible to war-like ideologies.  Nevertheless, there may be something in it.  As a thought experiment, imagine that the combatants in Europe's ideology-fueled 17th century bloodbath, the Thirty Years War, had each been given the nuclear bomb on the eve of the war's beginning in 1618.  It is at least imaginable that the sheer horror of nuclear war would have motivated them to negotiate an armed truce sooner than they in fact did, prompted by sheer exhaustion, in 1648.

However, whether this is plausible or not is a somewhat academic point.  The argument we are considering here was a popular argument at the height of the Cold War, but is less often heard today.  I think this is because there now seems so little hope that nuclear weapons could ever be fully got rid of.  Therefore, we have just got to live in a nuclear world anyway, regardless of whether there are fewer conventional wars because of it or not.  I conclude that our fourth argument for the renewal of deterrence lacks persuasive force.

3.5: Climate change implies an uncertain future for the world

I think that this is much the strongest of the positive arguments for the retention of the deterrent.  As of 2013, it seems most unlikely that the world will meet its target of limiting global warming to within 2 degrees celcius compared with pre-industrial times.  This failure will most likely lead to severe disruption of the existing international order in the coming decades, as climates change, crops fail, and excessive summer heat threatens to make large areas of the globe uninhabitable.  We can reasonably expect that this may well increase international tensions - even that it may reverse the trend of the past few centuries to diminishing incidence of human-on-human violence generally.  In this new world it would be unwise for Britain to depend too heavily on the USA for its security, as US interests may come to differ from Europe's, not least because the wide geographical separation means that climate change may affect the two continents differently.

So, is this argument so powerful that it actually demands a stronger conclusion than the one towards which I have, thus far, been groping?  That is, if the climate threat is so serious, shouldn't Britain keep the full weapons capability that it has now, rather than the half-way house capability argued for in sections 2.2, 2.3 and 3.3 above?  Actually, no - because two considerations tell decisively against the more drastic conclusion.

Firstly, there are still no likely adversaries out there who in the near-future could launch a mass co-ordinated nuclear strike against the UK, such as would disable it from retaliating, and hence no need for continuous at-sea deterrence.  Secondly, climate change is not expected to happen suddenly; so, if it does produce a more dangerous security environment it will do this gradually, so that reducing our capability now will still leave us with enough time to re-expand our capabilities later should the need arise.  It would, however, be better not to get rid of our capability altogether, as the loss of skills and infrastructures involved would make that a more difficult decision to reverse.

Summary and Conclusion

Considering the arguments against ever using nuclear deterrence on principle, I have argued that:
  • unilateral disarmament would not promote universal disarmament, because it would most likely be understood by others as either incomprehensible, or else a sign of weakness.
  • attempts to emotively link the issue of deterrence to other global problems, such as hunger, are misguided, because the defence of its own citizens is the first duty of any government.
  • international law does not clearly forbid the ownership (or even the use) of nuclear weapons (although the correct interpretation of the law is a matter of dispute).  In my opinion, it should only limit their use to occasions of dire national or international emergency, such as World War II.
  • moral law does not clearly forbid the use of nuclear weapons in all circumstances, e.g. use of the bomb at Hiroshima appears to have led to a net reduction in loss of life, taking into account the many lives that would have been lost in an invasion of the Japanese mainland.
The first batch of arguments thus suggested no reason not to renew.  Considering the more pragmatic arguments against Britain deciding to renew its nuclear deterrent in its 2016 official review, I have argued that:
  • we should not aim to become just like those other countries that do not have the bomb, because that would involve casting aside too much history and tradition.
  • although the form in which we have nuclear deterrence at the moment has been conditioned by the nature of the threat from the Soviet Union, there are still threats in the present and in the future that require the use of deterrence (albeit in a less expensive form).
  • the sheer cost of the systems has become a problem for us, owing to the general need for austerity.
The pragmatic considerations thus suggest renewal in cheaper form.  So, could a consideration of some of the most popular arguments for deterrence pull the argument back the other way, towards full renewal?  No, because:
  • nuclear weapons do not in fact buy us a seat at the top table, because these seats are not for sale - the reform of international institutions to reflect the rise of the former "third world" is simply inevitable.
  • we should not commit to a 20-year, £25bn project merely in order to save what would at most be a few thousand people from having to re-train in new careers.
  • rogue states, although a real threat, are unlikely ever to be able to pose the existential threat to the UK once posed by the Soviet Union.
  • people no longer see a close relationship between nuclear weapons and the incidence of conventional war.
  • climate change will take time, giving us leeway to increase our deterrent capability later if the international security situation starts to deteriorate.
...all of which leads us to the (somewhat boring, I'm afraid) conclusion: Britain should use the Trident renewal process to downscale to a cheaper system of nuclear deterrence - perhaps one based on two, rather than four, submarines.  

One final point to note is that most of the arguments to this conclusion will also apply to France, which therefore may well also be in the market for downsizing its deterrent.  This suggests that it would be a good idea for the two countries to extend their recent (2010) Lancaster House treaty on mutual military co-operation to cover nuclear deterrence (it already covers some aspects of nuclear stockpile maintenance).  Although there is some loss of national sovereignty involved in such collaboration this can be considered low-risk, as the countries have already been joint members of the EU since 1973, are closely connected by trade and geographical ties (e.g. the channel tunnel).  Geographical closeness also lessens the likelihood that either climate change or geopolitical developments will have drastically different effects on the two countries.  An Anglo-French deterrent might also be a candidate for a "nuclear sharing" arrangement with other EU states, similar to the current arrangements within NATO whereby Germany and Italy gain some access to decision making about nuclear weapons policy in return for help in providing delivery and storage systems.  Such an arrangement could help further dilute the cost for Britain and France, whilst giving the other countries a share of the nuclear security umbrella.


Thursday 4 April 2013

The LibDems in Northern England in 2015

Ever since that love-in in the Number Ten Rose Garden back in May 2010, the Liberal Democrats have been wildly unpopular in the North of England. Many Northerners have long felt a strong tribal hostility to the Tory Party, which from that moment was transferred to the LibDems. It doesn't help matters for them that leader Nick Clegg looks and sounds like a posh Southerner (which to be fair, he is). Subsequently, broken promises on university tuition fees have helped to turn Clegg into something approaching a hate figure in Northern university towns like Manchester, Liverpool, Leeds and Sheffield or at any rate, so goes conventional wisdom

All this has given rise to speculation that the Liberal Democrats may be on course for a total wipe-out in the North in the upcoming General Election of 2015, a little like the wipeout the Conservatives suffered in Scotland in 1997, when they won none at all of the 72 seats on offer there (they have since recovered slightly, and now hold one seat in Scotland). Such an outcome is eagerly anticipated by many Labour grassroots activists, who have never shared the friendship towards the LibDems expressed by some of the Party's intellectuals and media backers, largely owing to local rivalries between the two parties based on council politics.

So, the conventional wisdom suggests some questions:
- Is a Northern LibDem wipeout in 2015 a likely outcome?
- Would this be a desirable outcome from a Labour point of view?
- If desirable, how highly should Labour prioritise its pursuit?

To answer the first question, we must first look at the 2010 General Election result. The North returned 154 MPs to Parliament at that election: 101 for Labour, 42 for the Conservatives and 11 for the LibDems. The 11 LibDem seats can be divided into two categories (the figures in brackets are the LibDem majorities):

Seats where the Tories finished second in 2010
- Berwick upon Tweed (2,690)
- Cheadle (3,272)
- Hazel Grove (6,371)
- Leeds North West (9,103)
- Sheffield Hallam (15,284)
- Southport (6,024)
- Westmorland and Lonsdale (12,264)

Seats where Labour finished second in 2010
- Bradford East (365)
- Burnley (1,818)
- Manchester Withington (1,894)
- Redcar (5,214)

What is interesting is that, although Labour finished second in only 4 out of the 11 seats in 2010, these 4 seats include the 3 most marginal; whereas the 7 seats where the Tories came second include the 5 safest. Given the strength of the backlash against the LibDems in areas where Labour are strong (as evidenced for instance in local council election results from 2011 and 2012) Labour can surely expect to gain at least Manchester Withington. Bradford East and Burnley are also realistic targets for Labour, although in both these seats there are complicating factors (of which more later). Taking Redcar looks like a tougher proposition (ditto) but is probably something the party would hope to do, given that Redcar before 2010 had a long tradition of electing Labour MPs.

But whilst it is just about conceivable that Labour could pull off a clean sweep of these 4 seats, it looks much harder for the Conservatives to take all 7 of their potential targets. This is not only because the LibDems defend larger majorities in those seats, but also because the way coalition politics has turned out means that the LibDems should not face any angry backlash from Tory voters, and indeed may be well-placed to actually pick up votes from the Tories. I can think of three reasons why Tory voters in Tory/LibDem marginals might be inclined to defect to the LibDems. First, kudos: the LibDems can now be taken seriously as a party of government at national level, in a way that was hard to imagine before 2010. Second, sympathy: the generally loyal attitude of the LibDems to the government may well earn them credit amongst Tory supporters. Third, liberal views: many Tory voters are pro-European and socially liberal, and for them keeping a LibDem in parliament may be the best defence against the eurosceptic, illiberal right-wing of the Tory Party. As against this, the LibDems are sure to lose some voters to Labour; but in all but one of these 7 seats (Leeds North West, which was Labour-held between 1997 and 2005), Labour has no real chance of winning, so tactical voting directed against the Conservatives may limit the extent of any such defection. Furthermore, 5 of the 7 (Cheadle, Hazel Grove, Leeds North West, Sheffield Hallam and Southport) are affluent metropolitan seats where the views of Tory voters could be expected to be relatively liberal, making it highly likely that there will be at least as many defections to the LibDems from Tories as there will be from them to Labour (or others).

So, we can now answer the initial question: "Is a Northern LibDem wipeout in 2015 a likely outcome?" Answer: no, it is pretty unlikely, although the LibDems do look set to lose between 1 and 4 seats to Labour and, more doubtfully, Berwick upon Tweed looks vulnerable to the Conservatives. The answer to the second question: "Would this be a desirable outcome from a Labour point of view?" is also clear: of course it would be desirable for Labour to take the 4 seats that they have a realistic chance of winning from the LibDems, and even more desirable to also take Leeds North West, as the Party would then be in landslide territory. But equally, it would not be at all desirable to see Liberal Democrats replaced by Conservatives, as, where that to happen, it would only make a Conservative majority government more likely at the expense of the likelihood of a hung parliament. I am sure most Labour supporters (that is, those that don't want to cut off the nose to spite the face) would rather take their chances with a hung parliament than with outright Tory rule.

That being the case, the third question needs to be re-worded to still be worth asking: "What priority should Labour give to campaigning in the 11 LibDem-held seats?" The best answer to this is to take them on a seat-by-seat basis.

Bradford East
With LibDem David Ward enjoying a majority of just 365 in 2010, it might be tempting to think that Labour are favourites to take this seat in 2015. However, local election results between 2010 and 2012 tell a different story. The left-wing Respect Party achieved a spectacular breakthrough in the 2012 council elections, following George Galloway's shock win in the parliamentary by-election in neighbouring Bradford West. Of the six council wards that make up Bradford East, two were safely Labour in 2010 - but while both saw increased Labour majorities in 2011, they were both lost to Respect in 2012. Of the three wards that elected a LibDem councillor in 2010, two continued to elect LibDems in both subsequent years, whereas the other (Ecclesfield) went Labour in 2011, but went back to the LibDems in 2012. The only ward Labour held in 2012 (Bowling and Bakerend) had been Tory in 2010, but saw the Conservative share of the vote collapse from 37% to just 11% during the first two years of the Coalition.

These results suggest a significant (but not overwhelming) backlash against the LibDems in 2011, which had largely faded by 2012. The more striking trend was the loss of Conservative vote share across the two years, from an average of 24% in 2010 to an average of just 8% in 2012. Bradford East seems to have rejected the Conservatives, but to be unsure who it wants to take their place out of the Labour, the LibDems and Respect. Therefore Labour will need a highly visible campaign here in 2015, with the result very much up for grabs.

Burnley
Before 2010, Burnley had been Labour ever since 1935, with Labour winning big majorities here even in years they did badly nationally (e.g. over 7,500 in 1987). But in 2010 Labour suffered from the expenses scandal, which implicated outgoing MP Kitty Usher, and lost the seat on an unusually big swing to the LibDems. Since then, the LibDems have fared poorly in elections to the local council (which has the same boundaries as the parliamentary constituency), losing 1 of the 6 seats they defended in 2011, and 7 of the 9 seats they defended in 2012. This pattern suggests that the LibDems may have been given some protection in 2011 by the memory of the expenses scandal; and that as this memory has faded they are becoming more exposed.

An additional complicating factor here is the history of popular support for the far right in Burnley. There was still (in 2012) a residue of support for the BNP, just short of 6% of the vote across the borough (down from 9% in the 2010 parliamentary election). There is, however, now no BNP representation on Burnley Council for the first time since 2002. This may well encourage erstwhile BNP supporters to switch their allegiance to the now up-and-coming UKIP. The BNP actually came first in terms of vote share in the 2003 local elections before losing ground steadily over subsequent years as their councillors gained a reputation for ineffectiveness. This history is likely to give UKIP the hope that, if it can get up a head of steam here, it could finish first, winning one of the party's first parliamentary seats.

Labour clearly need a strong campaign here, aimed at winning back trust; and should probably regard UKIP as the main threat if the LibDems continue to fade at the 2014 local elections.

Manchester Withington
This seat has a significant student population, who would have been attracted in 2010 by the LibDem pledge not to increase university tuition fees. Although John Leech personally kept his pledge to vote against the increase in the House of Commons, it seems unlikely that he will escape the backlash against his party over the trebling of fees. Local election results make grim reading for the LibDems: in 2010 6 of the 7 wards that make up this seat elected LibDem councillors; in both 2011 and 2012 all 7 wards elected Labour councillors. If that trend continues in the next local elections due in 2014, then the LibDems will have lost all 17 of their 2010 contingent of councillors from this seat. Even allowing for the propensity of voters to use mid-term local elections to punish the government of the day, this represents an unusually strong reaction. It also suggests that the putative LibDem strategy of treating the next General Election as a series of independent local campaigns is unlikely to work here, as Withington's voters are seemingly putting national issues ahead of local issues even in elections to the local Council. Another problem for the LibDems is the widespread perception that the Coalition Government has handed out disproportionately harsh financial settlements to the City of Manchester in local government spending rounds. In short, the LibDems look truly doomed here.

Redcar
The Redcar constituency is something of a special case, owing to the saga surrounding the town's (former) major employers, the Corus steelworks. The steelworks closed its doors due to the recession just weeks before the last General Election with the loss of a thousand jobs, and voters responded by electing Ian Swales with the highest swing against Labour in any seat nationwide. Swales now defends a solid majority of over 5,000 - and what is more, some work has returned to the former Corus (now SSI) steelworks, making his position even stronger. Moreover, local council election results do not suggest any post-2010 backlash against the LibDems is taking place here. The Redcar constituency is made up of 14 wards who between them send 38 councillors to the Redcar and Cleveland Unitary Authority Council, all 38 being elected once every 4 years. The party balance amongst those elected in 2007 was: Labour 19, LibDem 13, Conservative 3, Independent 3. In 2011 the balance was: Labour 20, LibDem 15, Conservative 1, Independent 2. This suggests that the LibDems have gained slightly at the Tories' expense whilst Labour have flatlined. I suspect Labour will have their work cut out to win this seat, and if they do pull it off it won't be by cashing in cheaply on rage against the LibDems. Nevertheless a strong campaign here is surely essential, given the seat's rock-solid Labour heritage.

Leeds North West
And here we have yet another peculiar case! MP Greg Mulholland is apparently invulnerable with a 9,000+ majority, and yet as recently as 2001 Labour held this seat with a majority of 5,000 whilst the Tories beat the LibDems into third place. Local council results show some evidence of an anti-Clegg backlash in 2011, but probably not strong enough to carry the seat to Labour. In any case the backlash effect appeared to fade a little in the 2012 elections. Headingly ward, where the effect appears strongest, produced a 1,927 majority for the LibDems over Labour in May 2010. At the height of Clegg's notoriety in May 2011, this became a majority of 438 for Labour; but in May 2012 Labour's majority in the ward fell to just 32. The other three wards that make up the constituency have remained in the same hands (2 LibDem, 1 Conservative) across all three years. So, although LibDem strategists are fond of repeating the mantra that "there is no such thing as a safe LibDem seat", Leeds North West looks pretty safe for 2015. Realistically, for Labour are unlikely to take this seat barring a national landslide that no-one (in 2013) expects, so there is no point in making it a high-priority target.

Berwick upon Tweed, Cheadle, Hazel Grove, Southport, and Westmorland and Lonsdale
These 5 seats can be lumped together for our purposes, as Labour has never held any of them. They also share the characteristic that their Labour candidates came third in 2010, with a maximum of 13.2% of the vote. These seats can be written off as hopeless from Labour's point of view.

Sheffield Hallam
If it was just down to the electoral arithmetic then Sheffield Hallam should be classified along with the 5 hopeless seats above. Just like them, Labour has never won this seat. The LibDem majority in 2010 was a whopping 15,284 - the LibDem's highest in the region; meanwhile Labour came third, trailing 3,812 votes behind the Conservatives. However, there is one factor that might seem to make the seat a special case: it will be defended by none other than Nick Clegg himself. This naturally gives rise to the thought that Labour should mount a strong campaign, mobilising all the students in the area to achieve the big (huge, actually) swing needed to get Clegg out of industrial Sheffield and send him on his way back whence he hailed from (Chalfont St Giles in Buckinghamshire, in case you were wondering). There is, however, just one small problem with this project - namely, that judging by local election results, the LibDems remain popular in this constituency.

Sheffield Hallam contains 5 council wards, all of which elected a LibDem in 2010. In the 2011 local elections, only one of these wards (Crookes) went Labour. The other 4 remained LibDem; Stannington ward with a wafer thin majority of just 5; the other 3 with decent majorities. In 2012, all 5 wards again elected LibDem councillors; Stannington with a majority over Labour of 284, Crookes with a majority of 540, and the others each having a margin over Labour of at least 889 votes. This picture is consistent with there having been a significant backlash against the LibDems post-2010, which has faded somewhat as time has gone on, and which was in any case never strong enough to put the parliamentary seat seriously at risk.

If it seems a little hard to believe that the still-deeply-controversial Nick Clegg should hold an effectively unchallengeable position in a city with Sheffield's proudly working class heritage, then it helps to explain it that the borders of the City of Sheffield are drawn in such a way as to include a lot of the surrounding countryside as well as the affluent outer suburbs, actually extending a long way into the Peak District National Park. For instance, stand at the triangulation pillar on the top of High Neb, at 458 metres above seal level and surrounded by grouse moors, and you are (rather weirdly) at the boundary of the City of Sheffield (and, by the way, Clegg's constituency). Other urban districts in England, such as Manchester and Birmingham, have not been drawn up this way - in those cases it is only the recognisably inner-city parts of the area that are classified as part of the official "City" and thus get parliamentary constituency names incorporating the city's name. Indeed, on a number of measures, the Hallam constituency is actually one of most privileged in the country (perhaps this is an under-appreciated factor in explaining why Clegg appears more at ease with the Conservatives than with Labour, but that is a topic for another post).

So, given that Labour can pretty much forget about any dreams featuring an enraged mob wielding pitchforks chasing the Deputy Prime Minister out of his his seat, what should it do? In any campaign, resources are limited - and especially so for Labour, who have recently struggled to match the Tories financially. Time and money spent campaigning in a seat you can't win means time and money not spent somewhere else where you could. So, whatever Labour activists feel about Clegg (and I personally think that, however badly he has let some voters down, he also has some very good personal qualities) the needs of the Labour Party will dictate that resources are not unduly wasted on Sheffield Hallam. This post has already identified Bradford East, Burnley and Redcar as being (for different reasons) in greater need of campaign priority. Besides these, the North also has much larger numbers (up to two dozen) of Tory-held marginals that could fall to Labour, and it will be the outcome in seats like these that will play the largest part in determining the identity of the next government.

Conclusion
I have answered the first of my three questions by concluding that the Liberal Democrats are highly unlikely to be wiped out in the North of England at the 2015 General Election. Indeed, they are quite likely to hang on to the majority of the 11 seats they currently hold in the region. My approach to the second and third questions, about the desirability of such a wipeout from Labour's point of view, and the priority (if any) that should be given to it, has been to argue from the local conditions in each seat to the need for a pragmatic response to variations in those conditions.

In any case, there is a sense in which it is meaningless for any party to adopt a "wipeout" strategy in relation to any other party. All three big mainstream parties in Britain field candidates in every mainland British seat, and there isn't a single seat they wouldn't prefer to win than lose, so in some sense they are all trying to wipe each other out at every election. Questions about strategy only become meaningful in the context of the need to allocate limited campaign resources between competing objectives, and any party that really wants to win (and isn't stupid) will always settle these questions by reference to local conditions in each parliamentary constituency, rather than some generalised desire to penalise some other party. Once the specific questions about tactics are posed which make the notion of a "wipeout strategy" meaningful, it becomes immediately obvious that any such strategy would be self-defeating.

On the way I have touched on some interesting questions concerning the direction of the Liberal Democrats political evolution under Nick Clegg, towards the centre-right ground that is increasingly disdained by the Conservatives, despite its being home to a large number of voters. The causes of this shift, and what it means for the future of British politics, are subjects I hope to explore at proper length in future posts.

Tuesday 2 April 2013

The Triumph Of The Political ClassThe Triumph Of The Political Class by Peter Oborne
My rating: 3 of 5 stars


N.B. If this review is rather long, that is because Peter Oborne's book raises a large number of issues that are very difficult to deal with briefly.

I find this book to be highly perceptive about some recent social trends affecting politics in the UK; also on the plus side, it is a real page-turner, written with caustic wit, and with a clear (and startling) message. However, although I thoroughly enjoyed reading it, and see much truth in what Oborne is saying, I am not at all persuaded by the central argument - that there is little difference between the three mainstream parties, and that the next big development in UK politics is therefore likely to come from outside the mainstream (Oborne is ambiguous about whether such a development is to be welcomed).

The first claim is fleshed out by Oborne as a story of the decline of the party system since the 1950s, when the Labour and Conservative parties could both boast 2 million members each (or more). The mass memberships from different sections of society sent MPs to Westminster as, effectively, delegates to represent their respective interests. The result was an authentic choice between opposing political outlooks based on the differing life experiences of people far from Westminster, underpinning a healthy democracy. The rot sets in when party membership starts to decline (somewhat oddly, Oborne doesn't venture any suggestions as to why this happened). This eventually results in local constituency associations becoming hollowed-out shells, powerless to resist the takeover of the parties by their national leaderships. Once all three of the major parties have been through this process, their respective leaderships naturally form a cartel, which is none other than the Political Class of the title. As the cartel sticks together on all major issues, General Elections become meaningless, and real politics is driven to the margins, leading to an increasing sense of alienation amongst ordinary people. Meanwhile, as the elite's confidence grows with the realization that it is effectively invulnerable, its rule begins to take on more totalitarian characteristics (e.g. curtailment of civil liberties, attacks on the independence of the judiciary and the civil service). The post-democratic era is characterized by low standards of conduct in public life, and equally low levels of competence in government - national decline only intermittently obscured by the techniques of "manipulative populism".

As I say, there were moments when he almost had me persuaded! But I think there are less alarmist explanations for the trends he identifies. The decline in mass membership of political parties can be put down to the fact that they have lost their function as social clubs; that is, most of the people who left were not activists, but people who went along to socialize, and have now found more exciting ways to do this; many activists have stayed and are still engaged in doorstep politics and local campaigning, just as they always were - at least if where I live is anything to go by.

The national leaderships of the parties certainly have much more leeway than in the 1970s to make policy independently of, say, party conferences; but this does not necessarily support the thesis that leaderships have declared independence from their memberships. On the contrary, in all parties the leadership is itself chosen in a more democratic way than was the case in the 1950s. Besides this, there are other powerful incentives for leaders not to neglect their core constituencies, e.g. the need to keep the activist base enthusiastic, the need to get the core vote out at elections (even in marginal seats, in which it is not the case that the electorate is composed mainly of uncommitted "floating voters", merely that the number of committed supporters of two or more parties is fairly evenly matched), and the need to treat sources of funding that remain reliable in hard times with due respect. The benign explanation for the increased freedom of leaderships to form policy is that making policy via party conference proved to be a hopelessly unwieldy way of doing it, which parties have had to abandon in order to avoid losing competitive advantage to those of their rivals that have already given it up (or never used it in the first place).

The inevitable (and healthy) struggle for competitive advantage amongst the parties also explains why their platforms can sometimes appear to get closer together over time. A potted history of Britain since 1945 will illustrate what I mean. First, a new ideological paradigm appears on the scene (1945; 1979) and is embodied by a radical government that sweeps a horrified, protesting opposition before it. Next, over time, some features of the paradigm become generally accepted (the NHS in 1948; private ownership of industry in the 80's), whilst others prove to become increasingly irksome (national wage and price controls in the 60's and 70's; underfunding of public services in the 80's and 90's). To win votes each party must move away from its initial, ideologically entrenched, starting point in order to keep up with the evolving consensus. Until a new paradigm appears on the scene the differences between the parties will tend to become more subtly drawn, at least in terms of the original paradigm. This is not necessarily unhealthy - it is merely symptomatic of the fact that there is no point in continually re-visiting issues that were settled years ago. A party that does try to live in the past in this way tends to lose elections, as Labour discovered in the 80's and the Conservatives discovered in the noughties). Furthermore, this setting aside of old issues creates space for previously-neglected issues to come to the fore, e.g. climate-change, immigration, gender-equality, press regulation, banking reform. Whether the parties are actually getting closer together or not rather depends on the perspective from which the party battlefield is viewed; from a vantage-point fixed in the past the parties will appear to converge as they move on from old issues; but from a vantage-point that keeps up to date it seems instead that the the battlefield has changed shape rather than shrunk. That Oborne's vantage point is out-of-time is suggested by his choice of political heroes - George Galloway and Jonathon Aitken - figures whose dearest wish is to relive, respectively, the battles of the 1940's and the 1980's.

I still have to deal with:
- the growing sense of alienation with politics amongst ordinary people
- the alleged totalitarian tendencies of the ruling elite
- the thesis of British national decline
- the forecast that a new movement may arise from outside the mainstream


Alienation From Politics

Oborne's description of this problem is very good, and I think he is right about some of the reasons for it, namely: the professionalization of politics, and increasing levels of corruption. His other reason - the lack of difference between the mainstream parties - I have already dealt with above. But what can we do about the first two causes?

On professionalization, I would pose the question: is this not something we would be better off just getting used to? After all, we've got used to professional athletics and even professional rugby union, so why not professional politics? As with the other two cases, the professionals in politics have tended to win over "amateur" opposition because they are just better than them at winning according to the rules of the game (getting the most votes after 5 years of pitiless 24/7 media scrutiny, in the case of politics). Because no-one in politics wants to lose, I don't see any easy way to reverse this professionalizing trend. I can also see a benign consequence, namely that voters - faced with a seemingly blander choice between similarly professional alternatives - will be encouraged to concentrate on the policy issues rather than merely deciding with which candidate they can most easily form a tribal identification.

If accepting the professionalization of politics sticks in the throat, then something that might sweeten the pill is that politicians are not the whole of politics. The media (including social media) are a powerful independent force, and are increasingly open to apolitical citizens who organize campaigns on the issues that concern them. The media are just as much "clients" of these campaigning citizens as they are of politicians, and of course the media also have to think all the time of their own clients - that is, us, their readers. The politicians only get to survive for as long as they can ride the media's bucking bronco, which involves combining a receptiveness to public opinion with the ability to mould it in a constructive way. I think Oborne recognizes this in a way, but whereas he calls it "manipulative populism", I would label it more optimistically: "leadership".

OK, so what about corruption? The first point to make is that Oborne is right to be concerned about corruption in British public life. The second point is that he is also right (on the whole) to point the finger at Tony Blair's premiership for undermining the traditions of due process that keep corruption under control. Where I differ from Oborne is that I don't share the part of his diagnosis that portrays Blair as the culmination of a trend that has its roots in the 1960's. Instead, I diagnose corruption as a perennial hazard in public life. After all, Asquith and Lloyd George were notorious, and that should be impossible given Oborne's picture of Victorian moral rectitude persisting till the 1950s. I am not saying Blair was a one-off; just that, from time to time, leaders will come along who take short cuts because they have an inadequate understanding of the role that the rules play in upholding fair play and decency. I think this problem has always been with us, rather than being, as Oborne has it, a recent phenomenon (interestingly, his epilogue on the Brown administration in the paperback edition acknowledges that Brown tried to restore cabinet government; and since then the Cameron administration has apparently stuck to the model of cabinet government).

I think it is also important to note that even the Blair Administration's record on standards in public life is not all bad. It was the Freedom of Information Act (2000) that allowed the scandal of MP's expenses (something else that had been going on for a long time) to be exposed, forcing MP's to tighten the rules. Also, if the point of comparison is supposed to be with the 1950's, then we should remember that that was the decade of the Suez War, the Mau-Mau concentration camps, and concealed scandals about unsafe nuclear power plants. My point here is that we might be seeing more corruption because we have got better at spotting it, rather than that there is actually more of it around. Another thought that reinforce this one is that the sex scandals that have recently surfaced concerning figures who were powerful in the 1970's would be unlikely to occur today, as it has simply ceased to be acceptable to use social position to extract sexual favours in the way that it was then. Whilst these optimistic thoughts should not let the Blair's off the hook, they do tend to undermine Oborne's thesis that corruption is on the increase in general.

Totalitarianism of the Ruling Elite?

I think Oborne is barking up the wrong tree on this one. Totalitarianism is normally characterized as a state of affairs in which every aspect of life is deliberately politicized (and polarized) by an all-powerful ruling elite. It is hard to see how New Labour can be saddled with this, whatever its other faults. On the contrary, one of Tony Blair's strongest points is that he is good at understanding the perspective of people who are basically apolitical (remember "Mondeo Man"? Plenty of other evidence of this trait can be found in Blair's memoirs). Britain today is not a highly politicized society (like Venezuela or Cuba, where leaders with totalitarian tendencies have left a divisive legacy), but a complex, multi-faceted society in which politics sometimes struggles to get the hearing it needs. Blair's talent was that he could (sometimes) get it that hearing. Oborne diagnoses that talent as something diabloical ("manipulative populism"), on the grounds that the Blair government invoked public opinion to challenge the functioning of established institutions such as the judiciary and the civil service. But, hang on a minute, isn't it the very idea of democracy to make just such a challenge possible? It is too easy (lazy) to diagnose totalitarianism any time some leader does something popular that you disagree with.


British National Decline

Approximately 1% of the world's population lives in Great Britain. But, in the last two-and-a-half centuries or so Britain has exercised an influence on world affairs out of all proportion to that. Why? Because the industrial revolution happened here and not somewhere else, giving us a huge advantage. Eventually, other countries were bound to catch up, as much of Europe and America did in the late 19th century, and much of the rest of the world is doing now. So in one sense, national decline is indisputably real. But I don't think this gives us license to wallow in self-indulgent negativity, as it is still very much open to us to improve our standard of living and way of life, even as we become just another "ordinary joe" on the world stage.

The recent very important work by Stephen Pinker ("The Better Angels of our Nature") demonstrates convincingly that the world is rapidly becoming a less violent place. This means that losing the military dominance that we had until WW2 need be no very bad thing for us. Instead it is open to us to redefine our identity in the way suggested by E.M. Forster in Howard's End:
Does [Britain] belong to those who have moulded her and made her feared by other lands, or to those who have added nothing to her power, but have somehow seen her, seen the whole island at once, lying as a jewel in a silver sea, sailing as a ship of souls, with all the world's brave fleet accompanying her towards eternity?

A new Movement from Outside the Mainstream

Well, we don't have to speculate about this prediction, as it has already come true - in the form of UKIP, the BNP, the Green Party and the Respect Party. But then these alternatives have (in some form) been there for a long time - it is just the fact that they have not generally been popular at the ballot box that accounts for the fact that we don't generally pay them too much attention. Indeed, as one of them (UKIP) has recently started to make inroads at the ballot box, so mainstream parties have started responding to its policy agenda, as should happen in a healthy democracy (whatever you think of UKIP's ideas). In theory Oborne should welcome this as an injection of "principle" into the mainstream, but somehow I doubt if he does.

In general, I find Oborne's apocalyptic tone puzzlingly contradictory. He complains whenever politicians trim their sails to the wind, but he also seems to regard the likely consequences of their not doing this (takeover by parties currently regarded as non-mainstream) as also being potentially sinister. Democratic politics has always been, and continues to be, a mutually educative interaction between governing elites and the wider public, and I think it is unhelpful to paint this interaction in relentlessly negative terms. If some of the main parties stand for something different than what they used to stand for, that is because they have chosen to move with the times and stay mainstream, rather than being left behind and become minor. I think this is a mundane, rather than a scandalous, fact of our political history.
View all my reviews

Wednesday 27 March 2013

Review of Wilkinson and Picket's "The Spirit Level"

The Spirit Level: Why More Equal Societies Almost Always Do BetterThe Spirit Level: Why More Equal Societies Almost Always Do Better by Richard G. Wilkinson
My rating: 4 of 5 stars


This book is easy to read, and highly thought-provoking. But I think the argument it presents is somewhat odder than is commonly appreciated - and a better appreciation of that oddness would probably act as a bit of a dampener to the enthusiasm with which it has been received amongst left-ish people.

For a start, Wilkinson and Pickett make explicit that they are not arguing for bigger government, but for greater income equality. They actually criticise spending on public services (such as health and education) on the grounds that they are "only partially effective", instead pushing redistribution as a cure-all that will improve health and education outcomes.

In UK terms this suggests that they disagree with the last Labour government's emphasis on, e.g. the schools rebuilding program and SureStart, and would have instead preferred the money spent on those things to have been spent on tax credits or welfare benefits, to redistribute it directly to the poor. It is far from obvious to me why this proposition should win automatic cheers from the left - which in turn makes me think that some praise has come from people who made only a superficial reading of the book.

I am also not convinced by the causal mechanisms that are supposed to be operating to ensure that greater income equality tends to result in better health & education outcomes. I have two doubts; the first about the direction of causation; the second about the precise mechanism at work.

The authors make a very strong argument that income inequality is positively correlated with a wide selection of social problems (mainly health and education related). They are of course aware of the old saw that correlation does not necessarily imply causation, but they have an answer, viz. that when one independent variable (income inequality) co-varies with several others (the health & education problems) then it is overwhelmingly likely that the former is the causal factor (unless there is some common cause at work - the authors consider various candidates and reject them all, I think convincingly).

But what they don't consider is that the health and education problems have a tendency to cluster, e.g. that someone with poor mental health is also likely to have poor physical health, and vice versa. If this is the case, then this makes it likely that a large part of the causal connection runs in the opposite direction to that which the authors suggest. This is because, if problems tend to cluster, then an increase in the level of problems (which presumably have a negative impact on people's ability to earn money) will reduce more people from middle-income levels to lower-income levels than from higher-income to middle (and so increase the amount of inequality) - and the opposite changes would to the reverse. This means that spending on health & education projects targeted on people with specific problems will actually reduce inequality - an important, intuitive, conclusion that Wilkinson & Pickett deny. If I am right about this then the policy mix practised by the last Labour government in the UK (some spending on health & education, some on redistribution via tax credits) is defensible after all.

Another thing about their argument against inequality that seems a little odd at first is that it depends on the effect that inequality has on people's psychological states, rather than on any argument about justice or efficiency as such. This leaves it open to the counter-suggestion that any psychological distress caused by greater inequality could be tackled in some other way than the redistributive measures they favour, e.g. therapy, promotion of stoic values by the education system. If it turns out that there is some good independent reason for thinking that toleration of inequality is conducive to social and economic well-being in general, even though it causes specific problems (e.g. stress), then it may turn out that the best all-round solution is to tackle the problems through targeted measures (e.g. therapy) rather than redistribute (and forgo any wider benefits inequality brings). Wilkinson & Pickett might, however, reply that their evidence for correlation between inequality and health problems suggests that no society has ever managed to pull off this alternative solution - as, if they had, then they would show up as an outlier in one of the graphs, with high inequality and low levels of health problems.

But in this case I am moved to wonder why mass therapy route has never worked? Is it that it has never been tried, or does the idea contain some built-in contradiction? This is all pretty speculative, but I think the latter is the more likely explanation. Elites have pretty strong incentives to encourage stoicism (docility) in the mass of the population, so they are not likely to overlook this option. I think the real problem is that as inequality-levels increase, governing elites and ordinary people become more sharply divided into two distinct tribes. As they listen to and trust each other less, so relations between them get worse, causing increased stress levels for both sides (although more so for the ordinary folk). Stoicism proves inadequate as a solution because it is unnatural for any people to submit to alien rule - and the elites begin to seem more like aliens as the gap widens. Rule by aliens is also inefficient - and hence stressful - because the rulers do not understand the ruled, and hence make elementary mistakes even when they are well-intentioned.

All of which is pretty much in the same ball-park as Wilkinson and Picket are in; so it is not so much that I want to contradict them on this point, but just to say that they could have been a little less simplistic about the causal mechanism at work, which they have running along fairly straight tramlines - from inequality to status anxiety to stress to health problems - whereas I think the interaction might be more complex, involving conflicts of power and interest between groups as stages on the way to the bad outcomes.

All the same, this is really no more than a quibble with a brilliant and important book.

Tuesday 19 March 2013

Thoughts on Andrew Rawnsley's "The End of the Party"

The End of the Party: The Rise and Fall of New LabourThe End of the Party: The Rise and Fall of New Labour by Andrew Rawnsley
My rating: 4 of 5 stars


This book certainly isn't short at 800-odd pages, so it is just as well that all blurb on the cover to the effect that it is a real page-turner is justified. Rawnsley creates a real sense of drama, and even tragedy, out of the story of Britain's Labour Government from its re-election in 2001 to its final defeat in 2010.

This book doesn't pretend in the slightest to be a general, or even a political, history of Britain in those years. Its focus is rather on the personal relations and political infighting at the very top of government - in a nutshell, the notorious "TB-GBs". Rawnsley's choice of emphasis is perhaps inevitable given the fame of his weekly political column in the London Observer based on similar material. But do the rest of us need to bother with these old squabbles, or can we safely leave their memory to political nerds?

One reason for making the effort is provided by the contrast between what was supposed to be going on in government according to the Party line swallowed by most UK media at the time, and what actually went on as revealed here (my assumption that the account is essentially accuracy can be justified by the thoroughness of the referencing, the impressive size of Rawnsley's contact book, and the "ring of truth" his story has throughout). Labour's leaders spent extraordinary amounts of their time, energy and politcal and emotional capital not on efforts to improve the public services they professed to love, but in an a secret, bitter struggle with each other for control of the government. In particular, whilst public Health and Education services were boosted by being given more money, efforts to reform the way they were delivered foundered on the factional infighting.

So what matters here is not just that the public's right to know about all this was partly frustrated, but also that the effectiveness of public service delivery was affected (this last point depends on another assumption - viz., that constructive high-level political input into things generally makes them better - but without this assumption I do not see how politics can matter at all).

Some important conclusions are suggested by these concerns. One line of argument might be that the toxic culture of infighting detailed here is stronger in the Labour Party than in its rivals, and so a reason why they should be preferred over Labour. Another line might be that the squalidness of the political process is a reason to minimize the extent to which politics impacts our lives, and hence a reason to reduce the role government plays in our society. Personally I am not persuaded by either of these lines, although I think a serious case could be mounted for either.

My own view is that the sad history of New Labour best supports the conclusion that Britain needs a radical rethink of its political system. Democracy is available in different flavours, and in Britain we have the more adversarial. The first-past-the-post voting system encourages the politically engaged to congregate into two opposing tribes who play up their inter-tribal rivalry whilst each suppressing any internal differences, because open discussion of the latter would undermine the contrast with the enemy that is supposed to motivate one's own side on to the effort needed to win power. The results are brilliantly documented in this book: Labour's heavyweights spent years slugging it out with each other in private about what should be the "dividing lines" between them and the Conservatives without ever coming to a clear conclusion. The policies that actually resulted showed a middle-way caution that, whilst not reprehensible in itself, belies the supposed advantages of the adversarial system (decisive government based on a clear contrast between binary alternatives). The more damning point is that the ability of the politicians to supply constructive input into policy was, if this history is to be believed, seriously limited by the intensity of their struggle with each other - an intensity that might (plausibly) be lessened if political differences were generally out in the open, as they tend to be in countries with more consensual political systems.


View all my reviews